Philosophy
in a New Key Revisited:
An Appreciation of Susanne Langer
Howard Gardner
Much of what we learn, even within
academic disciplines, is picked up as general wisdom, as ideas that are “in the
air”; such knowledge can be absorbed simply as a part of breathing in an
intellectual atmosphere. Certain ideas and concepts are acquired in more
specific situations, in textbooks, discussion groups, or formal courses, only
to have their sources forgotten once the “point” has been absorbed. Just
a small part of our knowledge retains traces from the moment of original
encounter—we remember certain “crystallizing” experiences, for instance, an
occasional lecture, a powerful poem, painting, or piece of music, a passage
from the Bible or the Iliad, and, infrequently, some pages from a path-breaking
work of scholarship, perhaps Sigmund Freud’s On the Psychopathology of Everyday
Life.
In the early 1960s, I, like many
other students of that time, encountered a book that had just such an enduring
influence on me. The book itself was physically unimposing: a thin Mentor
paperback, its cover bordered with bands of gold and decorated with an odd
montage consisting of a lyre, a dragon, and a Socratic figure. But the
book’s content was riveting, its messages memorable. As I turned its pages with
mounting excitement, I felt myself confronting a set of issues that I had but
dimly sensed before, posed in a way that made sense to me. The work, Philosophy in a New Key, by philosopher Susanne Langer, led
me to other books, including those by Langer’s mentor, Ernst Cassirer, and to
other courses, including one given by Nelson Goodman, and eventually helped
determine my major scholarly interest—the study of human symbolic activity.
I think Langer’s slender volume had
an equally potent influence on dozens, perhaps hundreds, of other students.
And yet the author is not widely cited; she is ignored or disparaged by a
significant number of philosophers, and, despite an imposing shelf of books,
she never gained a permanent position at a major university. These
thoughts pervaded my consciousness as I returned to the book, several years
after the initial encounter, to discover whether separation had diluted or
reinforced the power it once held over me, and in the process to ponder the justice
of the fate met by its author.
Writing in 1941, Susanne Langer
surveyed the entire philosophical tradition, from the days of the pre-Socratic
philosophers to the rise of science in the nineteenth century. As she saw
it, a whole set of issues—the central philosophical agenda of days past—had
been invalidated by the emphasis on science. The nature of truth, of
value, of beauty, had been ruled “out of court,” the bifurcation of mind and
body was no longer taken seriously; with positivism at the helm, there was
tolerance only for hard, material facts and no niche for ideas, emotions,
values. Amid this impatience with anything immaterial, Langer spotted a
paradox. The very empiricists who scorned all matters of mind held in
special regard a group of individuals (mathematicians) who worked with the most
abstract, least tangible of all elements—numerical symbols.
Mathematicians were “special”
because they made no claim to be illuminating the issues of real life or the
structure of the physical world. They dealt exclusively with another
level of discourse—that of symbolic meaning. It was this symbolic domain
that began, at the end of the nineteenth century, to take hold of the
philosophical community. In fact, a dominant trend in philosophy at the
time Langer was writing entailed an obsession with symbols, one as pervasive as
earlier philosophers’ preoccupation with the senses of man and the raw matter
of the physical world.
The new agenda, the recently cut key
of philosophy, consisted of a concern with all manner of symbols-words,
numbers, and other abstract forms—and with the various meanings that underlie
our dreams, fill our imaginations, and draw us to treasure works of
civilization, ranging from the Parthenon to the string quartets of Beethoven. As
Langer put it inPhilosophy in a New Key, in an effort to contrast her
vision of meaning with that of earlier times:
But between the facts run the
threads of unrecorded reality, momentarily recognized, wherever they come to
the surface . . . the bright, twisted threads of symbolic envisagement,
imagination, thought-memory and reconstructed memory, belief beyond experience,
dream, make-believe, hypothesis, philosophy—the whole creative process of
ideation, metaphor, and abstraction that makes human life an adventure in
understanding. (pp. 236-237)
Now these ideas, this new key, were
already in the air at the time Langer wrote. Few of the ideas she put
forth in her work were wholly new. Indeed, Langer takes great care to
cite and pay tribute to a raft of predecessors: semiotician Charles Peirce;
neurologist Kurt Goldstein; the students of language, I. A. Richards and Wilbur
Urban; philosophers Rudolf Carnap and Ludwig Wittgenstein; her own professor,
the great logician and metaphysician, Alfred North Whitehead; and, above all, the man who had
some dozen years before completed a three-volume study of symbolic forms, the
redoubtable epistemologist Ernst Cassirer
In fact, a trove of articles and
books had been a prelude to this new key, but it would be a gross injustice to
relegate Langer’s work to the level of “mere” popularization. It was
popularization, but it was much more. In the tradition of the finest
educational syntheses, Langer drew illuminating connections among works whose
relationships had not yet been seen, avoided the perils of arid formulas and
moist metaphysics, and placed the entire movement in a historical and
philosophical perspective that had not yet been articulated. Moreover—and
here lies her claim to originality—Langer articulated concepts that clarified
issues in a still uncharted philosophical region and raised questions that are
still being pondered.
The basic argument of Philosophy in a New Key is disarmingly simple, and given the
hindsight of today, it seems much less arresting than it was on publication or
even at the time I first encountered it. Langer posited a basic and
pervasive human need to symbolize, to invent meanings, and to invest meanings
in one’s world. It was a property of the human mind to search for and to find
significances everywhere, to transform experience constantly to uncover new
meanings. But the symbols wrought by the human mind were not all of the
same sort and Langer found it necessary to distinguish two kinds.
Consider, as an example, the
proposition “George Washington chopped down a cherry tree.” Its meaning
can be conveyed in two contrasting ways. The first, called discursive symbolism, involves the expression of this
idea in words or other kinds of “languages.” One notes the meaning of
each term, combines them according to accepted rules of syntax, and arrives at
a commonly shared meaning. Most familiar ideas and notions could be
expressed in such coin.
Opposed to discursive symbolism is
another, less understood variety, which Langer labeled presentational
symbolism. Here, an equivalent idea could be gleaned from a picture.
Such pictorial symbols do not yield meaning through a sum of their parts,
for there are no reliably discriminable parts. They present themselves
and must be apprehended as a whole; moreover, they operate primarily through
shades of meaning, nuances, connotations, and feelings (the appearance of the
lad, the force of the blow, the ambience that day), rather than through a
discrete, translatable message. Any consideration of the meanings with
which our lives are wrapped must take into account at least these two kinds of
symbol, the meanings they bear, how they work, their special geniuses.
For most readers the distinction
between these two forms of symbol was the key concept of philosophy’s new key.
In introducing this contrast, Langer identified an important set of
similarities (both express meanings) and differences (they operate in
fundamentally contrasting ways) between words or mathematics on one hand, and
pictures, sculpture, and dance on the other. She broached the possibility
of analyzing feelings, emotions, and other intangible elements of human
experience through the relatively public arena of symbol analysis.
Clearly, she had helped to solidify an appealing intuition, and by
categorizing and analyzing it, offered others the chance to dissect it.
This aspect of Langer’s work has
undergone considerable criticism at the hands of her colleagues in philosophy.
Because she offered no strict definition, it is difficult to identify
examples of the two forms of symbolism with reliability or to be certain that
there are only two such forms. And, even more damagingly, Langer’s own
examples were wanting. Language itself can operate in a discursive or
presentational way (compare a textbook with a poem), even as pictures may wear
a different symbolic garb (compare a portrait with a map or diagram).
Critics with a more finicky, less intuitive approach than Langer’s have
had a field day challenging this distinction. Even those with a much more
sympathetic eye have gone on to adopt more carefully worked out distinctions
among symbol systems, such as those introduced by the philosopher Nelson
Goodman.
Langer’s purpose, however, was less
to glorify this distinction than to see where she could apply it. So she
sought to identify the origins of the various symbols that pervade the life of
our culture. In separate far-ranging chapters she examined the
evolutionary beginnings of symbolic activity in the thought patterns of animals
and young children; the cultural beginnings of symbolism in the realms of myth
and ritual; and the heights achieved by presentational symbolism in such art
forms as music. These chapters are at best uneven. Many analysts
have despaired of accounting for the origin of myth or rituals because the
possibility of verification is so slim. Investigation of the symbol
systems used by children and animals, barely broached in 1940, is now
sufficiently advanced to render her empirical statements dubious. An air
of the treatises of the late nineteenth century, when authors felt compelled
(and entitled) to comment on every aspect of the rise of civilization, is not
entirely absent from Langer’s synoptic work.
But amid these somewhat
disappointing chapters stands one that has exerted a tremendous influence on
many individuals: Langer’s account of the significance of music. Langer
rightly sensed that music was a symbolic system but that it did not directly
communicate either reference (for example, the sound of waves) or feelings (for
example, the composer’s own sense of happiness or anger). She proposed
that what music presented was the “forms of feelings”—the tensions,
ambiguities, contrasts, and conflicts that permeate our feeling life but do not
lend themselves to description in words or logical formulas. The composer
presents in spaced tones his knowledge of the whole of human feeling life, and
such nonarticulate symbols constitute the appeal and mystery of music. In
a passage that conveys the seductive appeal as well as the maddening ambiguity
of her prose, the philosopher suggests:
The real power of music lies in the
fact that it can be “true” to the life of feeling in a way that language
cannot; for its significant forms have that ambivalence of content which words cannot have.
. . . Music is revealing, where words are obscuring, because it can have not
only a content, but a transient play of contents. It can articulate
feelings without becoming wedded to them. The assignment of meanings is a
shifting, kaleidoscopic play, probably below the threshold of consciousness,
certainly outside the pale of discursive thinking. The imagination that
responds to music is personal and associative and logical, tinged with affect,
tinged with bodily rhythm, tinged with dream, butconcerned with a wealth of formulations for
its wealth of wordless knowledge, its whole knowledge of emotional and organic
experience, of vital impulse, balance, conflict, the ways of living and dying
and feeling. Because no assignment of meaning is conventional, none is
permanent beyond the sound that passes; yet the brief association was a flash
of understanding. The lasting effect is, like the first effect of speech
on the development of the mind, to make things conceivable rather than to store up
propositions. (pp. 206-207)
Taking music as the prototype of the
arts, Langer suggested that this knowledge of feeling life constitutes the
perennial attraction of artistic symbols; herein lie the reasons we treasure
those statements and works that to the logical empiricist have no meaning at
all.
Langer’s concluding pages assessed
trends in the world at the time of her writing. At the start of the most
awful war in human history, it is scarcely surprising that Langer painted a
gloomy portrait of “the fabric of meaning” in her society. She saw a
world in which language was lauded above everything; where the inner life was
disparaged, ignored, even destroyed. Drawing on her own analysis, she
emphasized the importance, the necessity of an existence in which various
levels of meanings and ranges of significance were tolerated. In place of
“a philosophy that knows only deductive or inductive logic as reason, and
classes all other human functions as ‘emotive,’ irrational or animalian,” she
proposed “a theory of mind whose keynote is the symbolic function . . . the
continual pursuit of meanings—wider, clearer, more negotiable, more articulate
meanings . . . the new world that humanity is dreaming of” (p. 246).
Were I her editor, I might have been inclined to tone down these
passages, but as a reader, particularly one thinking back to his college days,
I resonate to these sentiments.
In large part Susanne Langer’s work
has accomplished its mission. Her ideas about symbolism, about meaning in
art as well as in science, about the nature of different symbolic forms, are
common coin; one need no longer read the little Mentor paperback (now reissued
at several times the original price by Harvard University Press) to find out
about them. Thus the book, reconsidered, has a historical importance—as
one of that small set of pedagogical classics that has affected a multitude of
students.
And yet the work retains a
timeliness. Langer’s graceful enthusiasm is engaging; the historical
context in which the “revolution” is set helps place in perspective
contemporary movements in the social sciences and the humanities; various
distinctions introduced and various analyses offered constitute a genuine
contribution to current discussions about human knowing. Because Langer
intelligibly linked the old and new traditions in philosophy, because she
legitimated a scholarly interest in symbolism and the arts, and because she
foreshadowed research in psychology and philosophy that continues today, her
work still carries a message.
And what of Susanne Langer
herself? In succeeding years she went on to write an impressive set of
books, volumes that plumbed with increasing depth the pivotal themes introduced
in Philosophy in a New Key. This effort culminated in Mind: An Essay on Human Feeling, without doubt the most
comprehensive attempt yet undertaken to establish a philosophical and scientific underpinning for aesthetic
experience. Langer has gone her own way in these works; no longer in any
sense popularizing, she has carefully studied relevant humanistic and
scientific texts and has not hesitated to tackle the grand topics—mind,
feeling, art—that frighten so many of her colleagues in philosophy. It is
not surprising that she is more popular at small liberal arts colleges than at
technologically oriented universities; more appreciated by old-fashioned
humanists than by newfangled scientists. And it is not difficult to
understand why, anticipated by earlier philosophers and succeeded by more
disciplined minds, Susanne Langer has never broken into the charmed circle of
mainstream philosophers. Yet this gifted philosopher, now nearing ninety,
remains an inquiring mind in the best sense of the word—a scholar blessed with
a powerful intuition, who knows no disciplinary bounds, who follows a problem
wherever it will take her, and who has the gift of articulating the concerns of
a generation of scholars and many generations of students. That she
cannot be catalogued may explain why she has escaped certain honors—even as it
suggests why she may transcend her time.
No comments:
Post a Comment